-Cosmoi

1.5 -Cosmoi

There are a variety of models of infinite-dimensional categories for which the category of “-categories,” as we call them, and “-functors” between them is enriched over quasi-categories and admits classes of isofibrations, equivalences, and trivial fibrations satisfying certain properties that are familiar from abstract homotopy theory. 1 In particular, the use of isofibrations in diagrams guarantees that their strict limits are equivalence invariant, so we can take advantage of up-to-isomorphism universal properties and strict functoriality of these constructions while still working “homotopically.” This motivates the following axiomatization:

Definition 1.5.1 -cosmos

An -cosmos K is a category that is enriched over quasi-categories, 2 meaning in particular that

  • its morphisms f:AB define the vertices of a quasi-category denoted Fun(A,B) and referred to as a functor space,

that is also equipped with a specified collection of maps that we call isofibrations and denote by “” satisfying the following two axioms:

  1. (completeness) The quasi-categorically enriched category K possesses a terminal object, small products, pullbacks of isofibrations, limits of countable towers of isofibrations, and cotensors with simplicial sets, each of these limit notions satisfying a universal property that is enriched over simplicial sets. 3

  2. (isofibrations) The isofibrations contain all isomorphisms and any map whose codomain is the terminal object; are closed under composition, product, pullback, forming inverse limits of towers, and Leibniz cotensors with monomorphisms of simplicial sets; and have the property that if f:AB is an isofibration and X is any object then Fun(X,A)Fun(X,B) is an isofibration of quasi-categories.

For ease of reference, we refer to the simplicially enriched limits of diagrams of isofibrations enumerated in i as the cosmological limit notions.

Definition 1.5.2

In an -cosmos K, a morphism f:AB is an equivalence just when the induced map f:Fun(X,A)Fun(X,B) on functor spaces is an equivalence of quasi-categories for all XK.

Definition 1.5.3

In an -cosmos K, a morphism f:AB is a trivial fibration just when f is both an isofibration and an equivalence.

These classes are denoted by “” and “”, respectively. 4

Put more concisely, one might say that an -cosmos is a “quasi-categorically enriched category of fibrant objects.”

Convention 1.5.4 -category, as a technical term
#

Henceforth, we recast -category as a technical term to refer to an object in an arbitrary ambient -cosmos. Similarly, we use the term -functor — or more commonly the elision “functor” — to refer to a morphism f:AB in an -cosmos. This explains why we refer to the quasi-category Fun(A,B) between two -categories in an -cosmos as a “functor space”: its vertices are the (-)functors from A to B.

Definition 1.5.5

The underlying category K0 of an -cosmos K is the category whose objects are the -categories in K and whose morphisms are the 0-arrows, i.e., the vertices in the functor spaces.

In all of the examples to appear in §1.7, this recovers the expected category of -categories in a particular model and functors between them. This is compatible with the Lean formalization of simplicial categories as “enriched ordinary categories,” which have a prior 1-category structure which is explicitly identified with the underlying 1-category of the simplicially enriched category.

The following results are consequences of the axioms of Definition 1.5.1. To begin, observe that the trivial fibrations enjoy the same stability properties satisfied by the isofibrations.

Lemma 1.5.6 trivial fibrations and conical limits

The trivial fibrations in an -cosmos define a subcategory containing the isomorphisms and are stable under product, pullback, and forming inverse limits of towers.

Proof
Lemma 1.5.7 trivial fibrations and cotensors

In an -cosmos, the Leibniz cotensors of any trivial fibration with a monomorphism of simplicial sets is a trivial fibration as is the Leibniz cotensor of an isofibration with a map in the class cellularly generated by the inner horn inclusions and the map [0]I.

Proof
Lemma 1.5.8 representable trivial fibrations

If EB is a trivial fibration in an -cosmos, then is Fun(X,E)Fun(X,B) is a trivial fibration of quasi-categories.

Proof

By a Yoneda-style argument, the “homotopy equivalence” characterization of the equivalences in the -cosmos of quasi-categories of Definition 1.3.15 extends to an analogous characterization of the equivalences in any -cosmos:

Lemma 1.5.9 equivalences are homotopy equivalences

A map f:AB between -categories in an -cosmos K is an equivalence if and only if it extends to the data of a “homotopy equivalence” with the free-living isomorphism I serving as the interval: that is, if there exist maps g:BA

\begin{tikzcd}  & A & &  & B \\ A \arrow[ur, equals] \arrow[dr, "gf"'] \arrow[r, "\alpha"] & A^\iso   \arrow[u, two heads, "\sim", "\ev_0"'] \arrow[d, two heads, "\sim"',  "\ev_1"] & \text{and} &  B \arrow[dr, equals] \arrow[r, "\beta"] \arrow[ur, "fg"] & B^\iso  \arrow[u, two heads, "\sim", "\ev_0"'] \arrow[d, two heads, "\sim"', "\ev_1"] \\ & A & &  & B
\end{tikzcd}

in the -cosmos.

Proof
Lemma 1.5.10

The equivalences in an -cosmos are closed under retracts and satisfy the 2-of-3 property: given a composable pair of functors and their composite, if any two of these are equivalences so is the third.

By the representable definition of equivalences and functoriality, Lemma 1.5.10 follows easily from the corresponding results for equivalences between quasi-categories. But we can also prove the general cosmological result without relying on this base case.

Proof

The trivial fibrations admit a similar characterization as split fiber homotopy equivalences.

Lemma 1.5.11 trivial fibrations split

Every trivial fibration admits a section

\begin{tikzcd}  & E \arrow[d, two heads, "\sim"', "p"] \\ B \arrow[ur, dashed, "s"] \arrow[r, equals] & B
\end{tikzcd}

that defines a split fiber homotopy equivalence

\begin{tikzcd}  E \arrow[r, "\alpha"'] \arrow[rr, end anchor = 165, start anchor = 30, bend left=20, "{(\id_E, sp)}"] \arrow[d, two heads, "p"'] & E^\iso \arrow[d, two heads, "p^\iso"'] \arrow[r, two heads, "{(\ev_0,\ev_1)}"'] & E \times E \\ B \arrow[r, "\Delta"'] & B^\iso
\end{tikzcd}

and conversely any isofibration that defines a split fiber homotopy equivalence is a trivial fibration.

Proof

A classical construction in abstract homotopy theory proves the following:

Lemma 1.5.12 Brown factorization lemma

Any functor f:AB in an -cosmos may be factored as an equivalence followed by an isofibration, where this equivalence is constructed as a section of a trivial fibration.

\begin{tikzcd} 
  & Pf \arrow[dr, two heads, "p"] \arrow[dl, two heads, bend right, start anchor=190, end anchor=70, "q"'] & \\ A \arrow[rr, "f"'] \arrow[ur, bend right=25, start anchor=30, end anchor=230, "\sim", "s"' pos = 0.6] & & B
\end{tikzcd}

Moreover, f is an equivalence if and only if the isofibration p is a trivial fibration.

Proof
Remark 1.5.13 equivalences satisfy the 2-of-6 property
#

In fact the equivalences in any -cosmos satisfy the stronger 2-of-6 property: for any composable triple of functors

\begin{tikzcd} 
& B \arrow[dr, "hg", "\sim"'] \\ A \arrow[ur, "f"] \arrow[dr, "gf"',"\sim"] \arrow[rr, "hgf" near start] & & D \\ & C\arrow[from = uu, crossing over, "g" near end] \arrow[ur, "h"']
\end{tikzcd}

if gf and hg are equivalences then f, g, h, and hgf are too. An argument of Blumberg and Mandell [ BM11 , 6.4 ] uses Lemmas 1.5.10, 1.5.11, and 1.5.12 to prove that the equivalences have the 2-of-6 property.

  1. More specifically, these classes form a category of fibrant objects à la Brown [ Bro73 ] .
  2. This is to say K is a simplicially enriched category (see Definition 1.4.1) whose hom spaces are all quasi-categories.
  3. This is to say, these are simplicially enriched limit notions, in the sense described in Definitions 1.4.6 and 1.4.10.
  4. Please help us find an html friendly version of the trivial fibration symbol.