-Cosmoi

1.7 Examples of -cosmoi

We briefly tour a few examples of -cosmoi. The following theorem should be quite difficult to formalize:

The full subcategory QCatsSet of quasi-categories defines an -cosmos in which the isofibrations, equivalences, and trivial fibrations coincide with the classes already bearing these names.

Proof

Two further examples fit into a common paradigm: both arise as full subcategories of the -cosmos of quasi-categories and inherit their -cosmos structures from this inclusion (see Lemma [ RV22 , 6.1.4 ] ), but it is also instructive, and ultimately takes less work, to describe the resulting -cosmos structures directly.

Definition 1.7.2 isofibrations of categories
#

An isofibration between categories is a functor f:AB satisfying the displayed right lifting property for the inclusion of both endpoints of the free-living isomorphism:

\begin{tikzcd} 
  \catone \arrow[d, hook] \arrow[r] & A \arrow[d, "f", two heads] \\ \iso \arrow[r] \arrow[ur, dashed] & B
  \end{tikzcd}

As the inclusion the domain of the free-living isomorphism is a retract of the inclusion of the codomain, and vice versa, lifting against either endpoints implies lifting against both endpoints.

Proposition 1.7.3 the -cosmos of categories

The category Cat of 1-categories defines an -cosmos whose isofibrations are the isofibrations. The equivalences are the equivalences of categories and the trivial fibrations are surjective equivalences: equivalences of categories that are also surjective on objects.

Proof

Similarly:

Proposition 1.7.4 the -cosmos of Kan complexes

The category Kan of Kan complexes defines an -cosmos whose isofibrations are the Kan fibrations: maps that lift against all horn inclusions Λk[n]Δ[n] for n1 and 0kn.

One of the key advantages of the -cosmological approach to abstract category theory is that there are a myriad varieties of “fibered” -cosmoi that can be built from a given -cosmos, which means that any theorem proven in this axiomatic framework specializes and generalizes to those contexts. The most basic of these derived -cosmoi is the -cosmos of isofibrations over a fixed base, which we introduce now.

Proposition 1.7.5 sliced -cosmoi

For any -cosmos K and any -category BK there is an -cosmos K/B of isofibrations over B whose

  1. objects are isofibrations p:EB with codomain B

  2. functor spaces, say from p:EB to q:FB, are defined by pullback

    \begin{tikzcd} [column sep=small] \Fun_B(p \colon E \fib B,q\colon F\fib B) \arrow[r] \arrow[d, two heads] \arrow[dr, phantom, "\lrcorner" very near start] & \Fun(E,F) \arrow[d, two heads, "{q_*}"] \\ \catone \arrow[r, "p"] & \Fun(E,B)
\end{tikzcd}

    and abbreviated to FunB(E,F) when the specified isofibrations are clear from context

  3. isofibrations are commutative triangles of isofibrations over B

    \begin{tikzcd} [row sep=small, column sep=small]
E \arrow[rr,two heads, "r"] \arrow[dr, two heads, "p"'] & & F \arrow[dl, two heads, "q"] \\ & B
\end{tikzcd}
  4. terminal object is id:BB and products are defined by the pullback along the diagonal

    \begin{tikzcd}  \times^B_i E_i \arrow[r] \arrow[d, two heads] \arrow[dr, phantom, "\lrcorner" very near start] & \prod_i E_i \arrow[d, two heads, "\prod_i p_i"] \\ B \arrow[r, "\Delta"] & \prod_i B
\end{tikzcd}
  5. pullbacks and limits of towers of isofibrations are created by the forgetful functor K/BK

  6. simplicial cotensor of p:EB with UsSet is constructed by the pullback

    \begin{tikzcd}  U \pwr_B p \arrow[d, two heads] \arrow[r] \arrow[dr, phantom, "\lrcorner" very near start] & E^U \arrow[d, two heads, "p^U"] \\ B \arrow[r, "\Delta"] & B^U
\end{tikzcd}
  7. and in which a map over B

    \begin{tikzcd} [row sep=small, column sep=small]
E \arrow[rr, "f"] \arrow[dr, two heads, "p"'] & & F \arrow[dl, two heads, "q"] \\ & B
\end{tikzcd}

    is an equivalence in the -cosmos K/B if and only if f is an equivalence in K.

Proof

Many, though not all, of the -cosmoi we encounter “in the wild” satisfy an additional axiom: 2

Definition 1.7.6 cartesian closed -cosmoi

An -cosmos K is cartesian closed if the product bifunctor ×:K×KK extends to a simplicially enriched two-variable adjunction

Fun(A×B,C)Fun(A,CB)Fun(B,CA)

in which the right adjoints ()A:KK preserve isofibrations for all AK.

For instance, the -cosmos of quasi-categories is cartesian closed, with the exponentials defined as (special cases of) simplicial cotensors. This is one of the reasons that we use the same notation for cotensor and for exponential. Note in this case the functor spaces and the exponentials coincide. The same is true for the cartesian closed -cosmoi of categories and of Kan complexes. In general, the functor space from A to B is the “underlying quasi-category” of the exponential BA whenever it exists.

  1. The stability of equivalences between isofibrations under pullback can be proven either as a consequence of Lemmas 1.5.6 and 1.5.12 using standard techniques from simplicial homotopy theory or by arguing 2-categorically.
  2. Note, however, that this axiom is not inherited by the sliced -cosmoi of Proposition 1.7.5, which is one of the reasons it was not included in Definition 1.5.1.